Tuesday, June 4, 2019
Peter Osbornes Analysis of Modernity
woodpecker Osbornes Analysis of contemporaneityGive an name of the precise fibreistics of modern time as outlined by Peter Osborne.The barrier modernness has become deeply contested in the last quarter of a century. The emergence of deconstruction as a hermeneutic tool of outline inclined sociologists, historians and philosophers to prefer the concept of post- contemporaneity as a designation of the present. Peter Osborne believes that on that point is little evidence that could plausibly justify this shift in terminology. He sets out to inquire into the philosophical dimensions of the term modernity and maintains that, once modernity is mum in its theoretical and conceptual complexity, the post-modern fails to display the necessary differentiating criteria that would make it a notion in its own right. At the heart of his investigation thus lies to strike the inconsistencies in other thinkers philosophical indication of modernity.The beginning chapter focuses on two interp retations in particular Marshall Bermans account of modernity and Perry Andersons critique of it.1 Three aspect takes centre stage in Osbornes analysis of modernity modernity as a category of diachronic periodisation (1), modernity as a quality of social experience (2), and modernity as a project (3).2 His thesis is that incomplete Marxism, as it animates Bermans account of modernity, nor Andersons critique captures the peculiar characteristics of modernity as a concept of laity. The essay will briefly recapitulate Osbornes rendering of Anderson and Bermans interpretation and then outline the semantic shifts that led to the conceptual ambiguity of the idea of modernity.Osborne notes first of all the more mundane characteristics of modernity. Philosophers and ordinary people alike would point the notion of modernity with a distinct span of time that is identifiable and suggests a particular form of periodisation.3 This specific type of periodisation however already gives rising to some unsettling conceptual questions, amongst others what modernity in essence actually represents a concept for bring ining the present, or a form of social experience. He notes that modernity is suffused with different forms of time-consciousness and that the laicity of periodisation lies at the heart of the sociological discipline insofar it allows sociologists to engage in cross-temporal comparisons. In fact it is sociology that benefited most from the transformations in the notion of temporality which are somehow reflected in the notion of modernity. Osborne captures the basic dilemma of how to comprehend spay in society done the lens of temporal structuresThe problematic character of these assumptions (on the nature of the present) comes into view as soon as the issue of change within the present is raised otherwise than as an extrapolation of developmental tendencies built into the family relationship between pre-given structural social types4This problem marks the po tential and limitations of sociological inquiry. Modernity is constant change within the present, but we can only understand it through the emergence and transformation of social structures. This may permit us to compare societies across the times but it feeds upon an obscure notion of modernity as an unproblematic form of temporality. What we loose through this sociological kaleidoscope of analysis is the certainty that the historical process is radically open. Osborne contends that Marxism as well as Postmodernism attempt to purify this problem and that both fail to succeed. Let us now turn to his critique of Marxism first.Osborne credits Marxism with a novel view of historical time. In a way, Marxism reconciles plausibly the concepts of change and temporality while preserving a notion of modernity as something distinctively different to all previous ages. At the core of Marxian analysis lies the modes of production, a starting point that is reminiscent of the sociological view. Osborne points however to the crucial difference between the two by noting that Marxism achieves the visionary fusion of constant change and modern times only at the expense of a historical determinism that undermines any sensible concept of history as an open and uncertain path. In this sense, Marxism fails even more than the sociological view of modernity to attune to the philosophical consequences of the dual characteristics of temporality in modernity that is denotes a form of time-consciousness and at the aforementioned(prenominal) time functions as a periodising category that has inscribed in itself various types of temporality.Bermans answer to this problem that pervades Marxism as a historical analysis of societal change is, according to Osborne, to replace the historical project of communism with the notion of a radically open future. Osborne remarks caustically that such an act of simple second-stringer lacks any justification.5Andersons critique of Berman then provides Osborne with a valuable counter-perspective. The crux of Andersons argument is that Bermans account of modernity fails to acknowledge the differentiated forms of temporal experience that are implicit in modernism as a series of movements.6 Osborne immediately points to the problem that such a critique would necessarily embroil two different usages of modernity. On one hand, Anderson would argue from the perspective of modernity as a designation of a historical phenomenon, whereas on the other hand, he would need to use modernity as a category for the analysis of historical processes. This conceptual discrepancy however invalidates, so Osborne thinks, the potency of his hypercritical remarks.7What neither Berman nor Anderson consider is the dual nature of modernity as historical reality and as a concept capable of creating a coherent whole through its periodising thrust.8 He concludes that philosophers must recognise the nature of the reflexivity of the historical experience. He w ritesFor there is something decidedly new about modernity as a category of historical periodisation namely, that unlike other forms of epochal periodisation , it is defined solely in terms of temporal determinants.9The key to reconciling these different aspects of modernity is what Kosselleck would term a Begriffsgeschichte, a history of the concept. Mapping the semantic change that the concept of modernity undergoes can provide us with clues as to its complex philosophical conditions. So while neither Anderson nor Berman consider the logic of modernity as a category of historical periodisation they fail to comprehend that modernity is not a chronological category (Adorno).10Kossellecks interpretation of the emergence of the term Neue Zeit (new time) hints, so Osborne believes, at the structure of temporality that characterises modernity in contradistinction to other forms of temporality in pre-modern times. The critical intervention occurred with the claim of the Enlightenment that the new times were marked by recognition of autonomous reason. Modernity thus acquired a sense of something qualitatively new. It provided for the first time in history a conceptual space for abstract temporality of qualitative newness.11While modernity could now be understood as a form of social experience, it also was seen as something that happened and continues to happen. While the latter was hinted at already in the process of the accumulation of capital as conceptualised in Marxs critique of capitalism, the former aspect of modernity now unfolded into two dimensions firstly, the experience of contemporaneity, and secondly, the experience of registering this contemporaneity in terms of a qualitatively new, self-transcending temporality.12 Osborne notes that thisis achieved through the abstraction of the logical structure of the process of change from its concrete historical determinants an abstraction which parallels that at work in the development of money as a store of valu e.13This would now complete Osbornes alternative interpretation of the relationship between temporality and modernity. As he summarily remarks Modernity is permanent transition. Modernity has no fixed, objective referent.14 In a critical addendum he analyses Habermas and Foucaults notion of modernity and concludes that both fail to distance themselves from the project of constructing incredible universal histories with cosmopolitan intent.15Modernity as Osborne outlines it in his critical review of various thinkers is inexorably tied in with the notion of progress that wrong allows the projection of peoples present as other peoples future.16 He thus closes the circle in returning to the fallacy of the sociological account of modernity, one that has exaggerates universalising discourses of progress. Consequently, the idea of decline has no purchasing power in these philosophically erroneous notions of modernity.BibliographyPeter Osborne. The Politics of Time. Modernity and Avant-Ga rde. London and invigorated York turnaround 1995Perry Anderson. Modernity and Revolution, in A Zone of Engagement, London and refreshful York Verso 1992____. The Notion of Bourgeois Revolution, in English Questions, London and New York Verso 1992Marshall Berman. All that is Solid melts into Air The Experience of Modernity. London and New York, 19831Footnotes1 Marshall Berman. All that is Solid melts into Air The Experience of Modernity. London and New York, 1983 Perry Anderson. Modernity and Revolution, in A Zone of Engagement, London and New York Verso 1992 Perry Anderson. The Notion of Bourgeois Revolution, in English Questions, London and New York Verso 1992 Peter Osborne. The Politics of Time. Modernity and Avant-Garde. London and New York Verso 19952 Osborne, Politics, p.5.3 Osborne, Politics, p.1.4 Osborne, Politics, p.2.5 Osborne, Politics, p5.6 Osborne, Politics, p.7.7 Osborne, Politics, p.7.8 Osborne, Politics, p.6 and passim.9 Osborne, Politics, p.8.10 Osborne, Politics , p.8.11 Osborne, Politics, p.11.12 Osborne, Politics, p.14.13 Osborne, Politics, p.14.14 Osborne, Politics, p.14.15 Osborne, Politics, p.16.16 Osborne, Politics, p.17.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment